Menoeceus 128-130

From Epicurus Wiki

Jump to: navigation, search

<<Prev | Letter to Menoeceus | Next>>

Καὶ 


Also  

διὰ 


for  

τοῦτο 


this (reason)  

τὴν 


  

ἡδονὴν 


[we say that] pleasure  

ἀρχὴν 


[is the] starting-point  

καὶ 


and  

τέλος 


end-goal  

λέγομεν 


  

εἶναι 


  

τοῦ 


of  

μακαρίως 


[living] blissfully  

ζῆν. 


  

ταύτην 


  

γὰρ 


because [we recognized it as the]  

ἀγαθὸν 


  

πρῶτον 


first  

καὶ 


and  

συγγενικὸν 


familiar [good]  

ἔγνωμεν, 


  

καὶ 


and (thus)  

ἀπὸ 


  

ταύτης 


  

καταρχόμεθα 


we begin  

πάσης 


every  

αἱρέσεως 


choice  

καὶ 


and  

φυγῆς, 


avoidance [from this]  

καὶ 


and  

ἐπὶ 


  

ταύτηv 


  

καταντῶμεν 


we return [to this]  

ὡς 


as  

κανόνι 


(the) rule  

τῷ 


[judging everything good] according to the  

πάθει 


feeling (of pleasure)  

πᾶν 


  

ἀγαθὸν 


  

κρίνοντες. 


  

Καὶ 


And  

ἐπεὶ 


since  

πρῶτον 


[this] (is the) first  

ἀγαθὸν 


good  

τοῦτο 


  

καὶ 


and  

σύμφυτον, 


innate (in us)  

διὰ 


for  

τοῦτο 


this (reason)  

καὶ 


  

οὐ 


[we do] not [choose]  

πᾶσαν 


every  

ἡδονὴν 


pleasure  

αἱρούμεθα, 


  

ἀλλ’ 


but  

ἔστιν 


(there) are (times)  

ὅτε 


when  

πολλὰς 


[we bypass] many  

ἡδονὰς 


pleasures  

ὑπερβαίνομεν, 


  

ὅταν 


whenever  

πλεῖον 


greater  

ἡμῖν 


  

τὸ 


  

δυσχερὲς 


discomfort  

ἐκ 


  

τούτων 


[may result for us] from them  

ἕπηται· 


  

καὶ 


and [we consider]  

πολλὰς 


many  

ἀλγηδόνας 


pains  

ἡδονῶν 


[preferable to] pleasures  

κρείττους 


  

νομίζομεν, 


  

ἐπειδὰν 


whenever  

μείζων 


(some) greater  

ἡμῖν 


  

ἡδονὴ 


pleasure  

παρακολουθῇ 


may result [for us]  

πολὺν 


  

χρόνον 


  

ὑπομείνασι 


once we have endured  

τὰς 


these  

ἀλγηδόνας. 


pains [a long time]  

πᾶσα 


[Therefore] every  

οὖν 


  

ἡδονὴ 


pleasure (is) [good]  

διὰ 


because [it has a]  

τὸ 


  

φύσιν 


[familiar] nature  

ἔχειν 


  

οἰκείαν 


  

ἀγαθὸν, 


  

οὐ 


[yet] not  

πᾶσα 


every (pleasure is)  

μέντοι 


  

αἱρετή· 


to be chosen  

καθάπερ 


Similarly  

καὶ 


  

ἀλγηδών 


[every] pain (is)  

πᾶσα 


  

κακόν, 


bad  

οὐ 


[yet] not  

πᾶσα 


every (one is)  

δὲ 


  

ἀεὶ 


always  

φευκτὴ 


to be avoided  

πεφυκυῖα. 


inherently  

τῇ 


  

μέντοι 


Instead [one ought to judge all these] (matters)  

συμμετρήσει 


by comparison  

καὶ 


and [by examination]  

συμφερόντων 


of advantages  

καὶ 


and  

ἀσυμφόρων 


disadvantages  

βλέψει 


  

ταῦτα 


  

πάντα 


  

κρίνειν 


  

καθήκει. 


  

χρώμεθα 


[because sometimes] we treat  

γὰρ 


  

τῷ 


  

ἀγαθῷ 


good  

κατὰ 


  

τινας 


  

χρόνους 


  

ὡς 


as  

κακῷ, 


bad  

τῷ 


  

δὲ 


while (other times)  

κακῷ 


bad  

τοὔμπαλιν 


inversely  

ὡς 


as  

ἀγαθῷ. 


good  

Translation

For this reason, we declare that pleasure is the beginning and end of the happy life. We are endowed by nature to recognize pleasure as the first and familiar good. Every choice and avoidance we make is guided by pleasure as our standard for judging the goodness of everything.

Although pleasure is the greatest good, not every pleasure is worth choosing. We may instead avoid certain pleasures when, by doing so, we avoid greater pains. We may also choose to accept pain if, by doing so, it results in greater pleasure. So while every pleasure is naturally good, not every pleasure should be chosen. Likewise, every pain is naturally evil, but not every pain is to be avoided. Only upon considering all consequences should we decide. Thus, sometimes we might regard the good as evil, and conversely: the evil as good.

Analysis

After subdividing the desires and their corresponding desiderata into his three categories, Epicurus proceeds with a core discussion of pleasure, the cornerstone of hedonistic ethics, and the one attribute of the sentient human being that Epicurus holds to be innate, and thus self-evident. Epicurus posits pleasure as both the starting point and the end-goal of a happy life: it is where we begin all our deliberations, by judging the various choices and avoidances available to us according to the criterion of pleasure; it is the final outcome of exercising critical judgment in this manner, as it leads in circular, self-fulfilling manner to a life of pleasure.

Epicurus is, however, deeply scrupulous about the application of the "pleasure principle", as he is cautious to warn against a possible, and even likely misunderstanding of his teaching as license for mindless, ad hoc pleasure-seeking. Prudent hedonism --the kind Epicurus taught-- sometimes requires that we contravene the immediate urge to seek pleasure and avoid pain as they stand before as as choices of the moment: if current gratification could lead to greater pain later (e.g. a drinking binge, and the hangover next day), it is best to shun the pleasure that lies before us; if a greater pleasure could accrue later (e.g. feeling agile and healthy after exercising), it is best to endure the strain and fatigue of a rigorous physical regimen. Thus the application of the pleasure-principle has to be "double-tested" against the requirement of duration. Besides, as per the admonition of the fourth item of the Four-Part Cure, it is not difficult to endure such self-imposed "pain".

The fact that pleasure, and thus the instinctive pursuit of it is innate in us, does not necessarily mean that each and every ad hoc pleasure should be pursued. A prudent person, who can deliberate rationally, applies the further requirement of a pleasure's duration before opting for or against it. The same principle (albeit, of course, inversely) applies to pain: although we are instinctively predisposed to abhor it, we accept it when it is brief, and the pleasurable after-effect superior.

Thus Epicurus outlines the basic mechanism of his hedonistic ethics as a sort of cost-benefit analysis: despite the superficial paradox of a hedonist speaking against pleasure and in favor of pain, Epicurus makes a logically compelling case for the fundamental tenet of his philosophy, the necessary and sufficient correlation of pleasure and prudence, lauded eloquently in Menoeceus 132.

Personal tools